Friday, December 19, 2014

Coordination, Efficiency, and the Coase Theorem

A recent post by Matt Levine starts out with the following observation:
A good general principle in thinking about derivatives is that real effects tend to ripple out from economic interests. This is not always true, and not always intuitive: If you and I bet on a football game, that probably won't affect the outcome of the game. But most of the time, in financial markets, it is a mistake to think of derivatives as purely zero-sum, two-party bets with no implications for the underlying thing. Those bets don't want to stay in their boxes; they want to leak out and try to make themselves come true.
Now one could object that you and I can't affect the outcome of a sporting event because neither of us is Pete Rose or Hansie Cronje, and that we can't affect credit events with our bets either. But this would be pedantic, and miss the larger point. Levine is arguing that the existence of credit derivatives creates incentives for negotiated actions that result in efficient outcomes; that the "Coase Theorem works pretty well in finance." 

To make his point, Levine draws on two striking examples in which parties making bets on default using credit derivatives spent substantial sums trying to make their bets pay off, using the anticipated revenues to subsidize their efforts. In one case a protection buyer provided financing on attractive terms for the reference entity (Codere), under the condition that it delay an interest payment, thus triggering a credit event and resulting in a payout on the bet. In the other case, a protection seller offered financing to the reference entity (Radio Shack) in order to help it meet contractual debt obligations until the swaps expire. The significance of these examples, for Levine, is that they are on opposite sides of the market: "the two sides can manipulate against each other, and in expectation the manipulations and counter-manipulations will cancel each other out and you'll get the economically correct result." 

Well, yes, if we lived in a world without transactions costs. Such a world is sometimes called Coasean, but it would be more accurate to describe it as anti-Coasean. The world of zero transactions costs that Coase contemplated in his classic paper was a thought experiment designed to illustrate certain weaknesses in the neoclassical method, especially as it pertains to the analysis of externalities. But the world in which these deals were made is one in which transactions costs are significant and pervasive. Given this, what do the examples really teach us? 

Transactions costs arise from a broad range of activities, including the negotiation and enforcement of contracts, and the coordination of efforts by multiple interested parties. In two party settings (such as the case of Sturges v. Bridgman explored by Coase) these costs can be manageable, since little coordination is required. But once multiple parties are involved transactions costs can quickly become prohibitive, in part because no stable agreement may exist. And as Levine himself usefully informs us, "there are a lot of credit default swaps outstanding on Radio Shack's debt, now about $26 billion gross and $550 million net notional." 

The two sides of this market are populated by multiple firms, each with different stakes in the outcome. For a single party on one side of the market to negotiate a deal with the reference entity requires that its position be large, especially in relation to those on the opposite side of the trade. The resulting outcome will reflect market structure and the distribution of position sizes rather than the overall gains from trade. The examples therefore point not to the relevance of the Coase Theorem, which Coase himself considered largely irrelevant as a descriptive claim, but rather to the fact that coordination trumps efficiency in finance. 

Saturday, September 06, 2014

The CORE Project

Back in October 2012 I got an unexpected email from Wendy Carlin, Professor of Economics at University College London, asking me to join her and a few others for a meeting in Cambridge, Massachusetts, to be held the following January. The goal was to "consider how we could better teach economics to undergraduates." Wendy motivated the project as follows:
People say that altering the course of the undergraduate curriculum is like turning around a half a million ton super tanker. But I think that the time may be right for the initiative I am inviting you to join me in proposing. 
First the economy has performed woefully over the past few decades in most of the advanced economies with increasing inequality, stagnant or declining living standards for many, and increased instability. Second, in the public eye economics as a profession has performed little better; with many of our colleagues offering superficial and even incorrect diagnoses and remedies. Third, what economists now know is increasingly remote from what is taught to our undergraduates. We can teach much more exciting and relevant material than the current diet... Fourth, the economy itself is grippingly interesting to students. 
I think that a curriculum that places before students the best of the current state of economic knowledge addressed to the pressing problems of concern... could succeed.
I attended the meeting, and joined a group that would swell to incorporate more than two dozen economists spread across four continents. Over the next eighteen months, with funding from the Institute for New Economic Thinking, we began to assemble a set of teaching materials under the banner of Curriculum Open-Access Resources in Economics (CORE).


A beta version of the resulting e-book, simply called The Economy, is now available free of charge worldwide to anyone interested in using it. Only the first ten units have been posted at this time; the remainder are still in preparation. The published units cover the industrial revolution, innovation, firms, contracts, labor and product markets, competition, disequilibrium dynamics, and externalities. For the most part these are topics in microeconomics, though with a great deal of attention to history, institutions, and experiments. The latter half of the book, dealing with money, banking, and aggregate activity is nearing completion and is targeted for release in November.

It is our hope that these materials make their way in some form into every introductory classroom and beyond. Instructors could use them to supplement (and perhaps eventually replace) existing texts, and students could use them to dig deeper and obtain fresh and interesting perspectives on topics they encounter (or ought to encounter) in class. And anyone interested in an introduction to economics, regardless of age, occupation or location, can work through these units at their own pace.

The unit with which I had the greatest involvement is the ninth, on Market Dynamics. Here we examine the variety of ways in which markets respond to changes in the conditions of demand and supply. The focus is on adjustment processes rather than simply a comparison of equilibria. For instance, we look at the process of trading in securities markets, introducing the continuous double auction, bid and ask prices, and limit orders. We examine the manner in which new information is incorporated into prices through order book dynamics. The contrasting perspectives of Fama and Shiller on the possibility of asset price bubbles are introduced, with a discussion of the risks involved in market timing and short selling.  Markets with highly flexible prices are then contrasted with posted price markets (such as the iTunes store) where changes in demand are met with pure quantity adjustments in the short run. We look at rationing, queueing and secondary markets in some detail, with reference to the deliberate setting of prices below market-clearing levels, as in the case of certain concerts, sporting events, and elite restaurants.

I mention this unit not just because I had a hand in developing it, but to make the point that there are topics covered in these materials that would not ordinarily be found in an introductory text. Other units draw heavily on the work of economic historians, and pay more than fleeting attention to the history of ideas. The financial sector makes a frequent appearance in the posted units, and will do so to an even greater extent in the units under development.

But far more important than the content innovations in the book are the process innovations. The material was developed collaboratively by a large team, and made coherent through a careful editing process. It is released under a creative commons license, so that any user can customize, translate, or improve it for their own use or the use of their students. Most importantly, we see this initial product not as a stand-alone text, but rather as the foundation on which an entire curriculum can be built. We can imagine the development of units that branch off into various fields (for use in topics courses), as well as the incorporation of more advanced material eventually making its way into graduate education.

So if you're teaching an introductory economics course, or enrolled in one, or just interested in the material, just register here for complete access without charge. We will eventually set up instructor diaries to consolidate feedback, and welcome suggestions for improvement. This is just the start of a long but hopefully significant and transformative process of creative destruction. 

Tuesday, August 19, 2014

The Agent-Based Method

It's nice to see some attention being paid to agent-based computational models on economics blogs, but Chris House has managed to misrepresent the methodology so completely that his post is likely to do more harm than good. 

In comparing the agent-based method to the more standard dynamic stochastic general equilibrium (DSGE) approach, House begins as follows:
Probably the most important distinguishing feature is that, in an ABM, the interactions are governed by rules of behavior that the modeler simply encodes directly into the system individuals who populate the environment.
So far so good, although I would not have used the qualifier "simply", since encoded rules can be highly complex. For instance, an ABM that seeks to describe the trading process in an asset market may have multiple participant types (liquidity, information, and high-frequency traders for instance) and some of these may be using extremely sophisticated strategies.

How does this approach compare with DSGE models? House argues that the key difference lies in assumptions about rationality and self-interest:
People who write down DSGE models don’t do that. Instead, they make assumptions on what people want. They also place assumptions on the constraints people face. Based on the combination of goals and constraints, the behavior is derived. The reason that economists set up their theories this way – by making assumptions about goals and then drawing conclusions about behavior – is that they are following in the central tradition of all of economics, namely that allocations and decisions and choices are guided by self-interest. This goes all the way back to Adam Smith and it’s the organizing philosophy of all economics. Decisions and actions in such an environment are all made with an eye towards achieving some goal or some objective. For consumers this is typically utility maximization – a purely subjective assessment of well-being.  For firms, the objective is typically profit maximization. This is exactly where rationality enters into economics. Rationality means that the “agents” that inhabit an economic system make choices based on their own preferences.
This, to say the least, is grossly misleading. The rules encoded in an ABM could easily specify what individuals want and then proceed from there. For instance, we could start from the premise that our high-frequency traders want to maximize profits. They can only do this by submitting orders of various types, the consequences of which will depend on the orders placed by others. Each agent can have a highly sophisticated strategy that maps historical data, including the current order book, into new orders. The strategy can be sensitive to beliefs about the stream of income that will be derived from ownership of the asset over a given horizon, and may also be sensitive to beliefs about the strategies in use by others. Agents can be as sophisticated and forward-looking in their pursuit of self-interest in an ABM as you care to make them; they can even be set up to make choices based on solutions to dynamic programming problems, provided that these are based on private beliefs about the future that change endogenously over time. 

What you cannot have in an ABM is the assumption that, from the outset, individual plans are mutually consistent. That is, you cannot simply assume that the economy is tracing out an equilibrium path. The agent-based approach is at heart a model of disequilibrium dynamics, in which the mutual consistency of plans, if it arises at all, has to do so endogenously through a clearly specified adjustment process. This is the key difference between the ABM and DSGE approaches, and it's right there in the acronym of the latter.

A typical (though not universal) feature of agent-based models is an evolutionary process, that allows successful strategies to proliferate over time at the expense of less successful ones. Since success itself is frequency dependent---the payoffs to a strategy depend on the prevailing distribution of strategies in the population---we have strong feedback between behavior and environment. Returning to the example of trading, an arbitrage-based strategy may be highly profitable when rare but much less so when prevalent. This rich feedback between environment and behavior, with the distribution of strategies determining the environment faced by each, and the payoffs to each strategy determining changes in their composition, is a fundamental feature of agent-based models. In failing to understand this, House makes claims that are close to being the opposite of the truth: 
Ironically, eliminating rational behavior also eliminates an important source of feedback – namely the feedback from the environment to behavior.  This type of two-way feedback is prevalent in economics and it’s why equilibria of economic models are often the solutions to fixed-point mappings. Agents make choices based on the features of the economy.  The features of the economy in turn depend on the choices of the agents. This gives us a circularity which needs to be resolved in standard models. This circularity is cut in the ABMs however since the choice functions do not depend on the environment. This is somewhat ironic since many of the critics of economics stress such feedback loops as important mechanisms.
It is absolutely true that dynamics in agent-based models do not require the computation of fixed points, but this is a strength rather than a weakness, and has nothing to do with the absence of feedback effects. These effects arise dynamically in calendar time, not through some mystical process by which coordination is instantaneously achieved and continuously maintained. 

It's worth thinking about how the learning literature in macroeconomics, dating back to Marcet and Sargent and substantially advanced by Evans and Honkapohja fits into this schema. Such learning models drop the assumption that beliefs continuously satisfy mutual consistency, and therefore take a small step towards the ABM approach. But it really is a small step, since a great deal of coordination continues to be assumed. For instance, in the canonical learning model, there is a parameter about which learning occurs, and the system is self-referential in that beliefs about the parameter determine its realized value. This allows for the possibility that individuals may hold incorrect beliefs, but limits quite severely---and more importantly, exogenously---the structure of such errors. This is done for understandable reasons of tractability, and allows for analytical solutions and convergence results to be obtained. But there is way too much coordination in beliefs across individuals assumed for this to be considered part of the ABM family.

The title of House's post asks (in response to an earlier piece by Mark Buchanan) whether agent-based models really are the future of the discipline. I have argued previously that they are enormously promising, but face one major methodological obstacle that needs to be overcome. This is the problem of quality control: unlike papers in empirical fields (where causal identification is paramount) or in theory (where robustness is key) there is no set of criteria, widely agreed upon, that can allow a referee to determine whether a given set of simulation results provides a deep and generalizable insight into the workings of the economy. One of the most celebrated agent-based models in economics---the Schelling segregation model---is also among the very earliest. Effective and acclaimed recent exemplars are in short supply, though there is certainly research effort at the highest levels pointed in this direction. The claim that such models can displace the equilibrium approach entirely is much too grandiose, but they should be able to find ample space alongside more orthodox approaches in time. 

---

The example of interacting trading strategies in this post wasn't pulled out of thin air; market ecology has been a recurrent theme on this blog. In ongoing work with Yeon-Koo Che and Jinwoo Kim, I am exploring the interaction of trading strategies in asset markets, with the goal of addressing some questions about the impact on volatility and welfare of high-frequency trading. We have found the agent-based approach very useful in thinking about these questions, and I'll present some preliminary results at a session on the methodology at the Rethinking Economics conference in New York next month. The event is free and open to the public but seating is limited and registration required.

---

Update: Chris House responds, leaping from the assertion that agent-based models disregard rationality and self-interest to the diametrically opposed claim that DSGEs are a special case of agent-based models. Noah Smith concurs, but seems to misunderstand not just the agent-based method but also the rational expectations hypothesis. Leigh Tesfatsion's two comments on Chris' posts are spot on, and it's worth spending a bit of time on her agent-based computational economics page. There you will find the following definition (italics added):
Agent-based computational economics (ACE) is the computational modeling of economic processes (including whole economies) as open-ended dynamic systems of interacting agents... ACE modeling is analogous to a culture-dish laboratory experiment for a virtual world. Starting from an initial world state, specified by the modeler, the virtual world should be capable of evolving over time driven solely by the interactions of the agents that reside within the world. No resort to externally imposed sky-hooks enforcing global coordination, such as market clearing and rational expectations constraints, should be needed to drive or support the dynamics of this world.
As I said in a response to Noah, the claim that DSGE's are a special case of agent-based models is not just wrong, it makes the case for pluralism harder to make. But the good news is that there seems to be a lot of interest in the approach among graduate students. I introduced the basic idea at the end of a graduate math methods course for first year PhD students at Columbia a couple of years ago, and it was really nice to see a few of them show up to the agent-based modeling session at the recent Rethinking Economics conference. I suspect that before long, knowledge of this (along with more orthodox methods) will be an asset in the job market. 

Tuesday, June 03, 2014

Plots and Subplots in Piketty's Capital

Thomas Piketty's Capital in the Twenty-First Century is a hefty 700 pages long, but if one were to collect together all reviews of the book into a single volume it would doubtless be heftier still. These range from glowing to skeptical to largely dismissive; from cursory to deeply informed. Questions have been asked (and answered) about the book’s empirical claims, and some serious theoretical challenges are now on the table.

Most reviewers have focused on Piketty’s dramatic predictions of rising global wealth inequality, which he attributes to the logic of capital accumulation under conditions of low fertility and productivity growth. I have little to say about this main message, which I consider plausible but highly speculative (more on this below). Instead, I will focus here on the book’s many interesting digressions and subplots.

When an economist as talented as Piketty immerses himself in a sea of data from a broad range of sources for over a decade, a number of valuable insights are bound to emerge. Some are central to his main argument while others are tangential; either way, they are deserving of comment and scrutiny.

Let me begin with the issue of measurement, which Piketty discusses explicitly. He argues that "statistical indices such as the Gini coefficient give an abstract and sterile view of inequality, which makes it difficult for people to grasp their position in the contemporary hierarchy." Instead, his preference is for distribution tables, which display the share of total income or wealth that is held by members of various classes. In many cases he considers just three groups: those below the median, those above the median but outside the top decile, and those in the top decile. Sometimes he partitions the top group into those within the top centile and those outside it; and occasionally looks at even finer partitions of those at the summit.

Using this approach, Piketty is able to document one of the most significant social transformations of the twentieth century: the emergence of a European middle class with significant property holdings. Prior to the first World War, there was scarcely any difference between the per-capita wealth of those below the median and the forty percent of the population directly above them; each of these groups owned about 5% of aggregate wealth. The remaining 90% was in the hands of the top decile, with 50% held by the top centile. This was to change dramatically: the share of wealth held by the middle group has risen seven-fold and now stands at 35%, while the share of wealth held by those below the median remains negligible.

Piketty argues that this "emergence of a patrimonial middle class was an important, if fragile, historical innovation, and it would be serious mistake to underestimate it." In particular, one could make a case that the continued stability of the system depends on the consolidation of this transition. If there is a reversal, as Piketty suspects there could well be, it would have major social and political ramifications. I'll return to this point below.

In order to facilitate comparisons across time and space, Piketty measures the value of capital in units of years of national income. This is an interesting choice that yields certain immediate dividends. Consider the following chart, which displays the value of national capital for eight countries over four decades:


The dramatic increase during the 1980s in the value of Japanese capital, encompassing both real estate and stocks, is evident. So is the long, slow decline in the ratio of capital to national income after the peak in 1990. The Japanese series begins and ends close to the cluster of other countries, but takes a three decade long detour in the interim. Piketty argues that the use of such measures can be helpful for policy:
...the Japanese record of 1990 was recently beaten by Spain, where the total amount of net private capital reached eight years of national income on the eve of the crisis of 2007-2008... The Spanish bubble began to shrink quite rapidly in 2010-2011, just as the Japanese bubble did in the early 1990s... note how useful it is to represent the historical evolution of the capital/income ratio in this way, and thus to exploit stocks and flows in the national accounts. Doing so might make it possible to detect obvious overvaluations in time to apply prudential policies... 
Over short periods of time the value of aggregate capital can fluctuate sharply; over longer periods it is determined largely by the flow of savings. One of the most provocative claims in the book concerns the motives for private saving. The standard textbook theory, familiar to students of economics at all levels, is based on the life-cycle hypothesis formulated by Franco Modigliani. From this perspective, saving is motivated by the desire to smooth consumption over the course of a lifetime: one borrows when young, pays off this debt and accumulates assets during peak earning years, and spends down the accumulated savings during retirement. Geometrically, savings behavior is depicted as a "Modigliani triangle" with rising asset accumulation when working, a peak at retirement, and depletion of assets thereafter.

There is no doubt that saving for retirement is a key feature of contemporary financial planning, and individuals with the means to do so accumulate significant asset positions over their working lives. But one of Piketty's most startling claims is that there is little evidence for Modigliani triangles in the data. Instead, asset accumulation appears to rise monotonically over the life-cycle. That is, the capital income from accumulated assets is sufficient to finance retirement consumption without appreciable depletion of the asset base.

Now this could be explained by a desire to leave substantial bequests to one's children, except that the pattern seems to arise also for those without natural heirs. Piketty concludes that "Modigliani's life-cycle theory... which is perfectly plausible a priori, cannot explain the observed facts---to put it mildly." This is a challenging claim. If it stands up to scrutiny, it will require a significant change in the manner in which individual savings behavior is conceived in economic models.

Also interesting is the aggregate savings behavior of societies. Countries that run large and persistent trade surpluses (thus producing more than they consume) end up accumulating assets overseas. Other countries are in the opposite position; a portion of their capital is foreign-owned, and part of their current output accordingly flows to foreign residents in the form of capital income. Not surprisingly, countries with positive inflows of capital income from abroad tend to be more affluent in the first place; Japan and Germany are prime examples. As a result, "the global income distribution is more unequal than the output distribution."

While such imbalances can be large when comparing countries, Piketty observes that at the level of most continent blocs, the imbalance is negligible: “total income is almost exactly equal to total output” within Europe, Asia, and the Americas. That is, the rich and poor countries within these continents have roughly offsetting net asset positions relative to the rest of the world.

The one exception is Africa, where nearly twenty percent of total capital (and a much greater portion of manufacturing capital) is foreign-owned. As a result, income is less than output on the continent as a whole, with the difference accruing to foreign residents in the form of capital income. Put differently, investment on the continent has been financed in large part through savings elsewhere, not from flows from surplus to deficit countries within Africa.

Is this a cause for concern? Piketty notes that in theory, "the fact that rich countries own part of the capital of poor countries can have virtuous effects by promoting convergence." However, successful late industrializing nations such as Japan, South Korea, Taiwan, and China managed to mobilize domestic savings to a significant degree to finance investment in physical and human capital. They "benefitted far more from open markets for goods and services and advantageous terms of trade than from free capital flows... gains from free trade come mainly from the diffusion of knowledge and from the productivity gains made necessary by open borders."

Unless African nations can transition to something approaching self-sufficiency in savings, a significant share of the continent’s assets will continue to remain foreign-owned. Piketty sees dangers in this:
When a country is largely owned by foreigners, there is a recurrent and almost irrepressible demand for expropriation... The country is thus caught in an endless alternation between revolutionary governments (whose success in improving actual living conditions for their citizens is often limited) and governments dedicated to the protection of existing property owners, thereby laying the groundwork for the next revolution or coup. Inequality of capital ownership is already difficult to accept and peacefully maintain within a single national community. Internationally it is almost impossible to sustain without a colonial type of political domination.
Indeed, the colonial period was characterized by very large and positive net asset positions in Europe. On the eve of the first World War, the European powers "owned an estimated one-third to one-half of the domestic capital of Asia and Africa and more than three-quarters of their industrial capital." But these massive positions vanished in the wake of two World Wars and the Great Depression. These calamities, according to Piketty, resulted in a significant loss of asset values, dramatic shifts in attitudes towards taxation, and a reversal of trends in the evolution of global wealth inequality, trends that have now begun to reassert themselves.

There are many more interesting tangents and detours in the book, including discussions of the circumstances under with David Ricardo first developed the hypothesis that has come to be called Ricardian Equivalence, and the manner in which the "long and tumultuous history of the public debt... has indelibly marked collective memories and representations." But this post is too long already and I need to wrap it up.

For a lengthy book so filled with charts and tables, Capital in the Twenty-First Century is surprisingly readable. This is in no small part because the author cites philosophers and novelists freely and at length. This lightens the prose, and is also a very effective rhetorical device. As Piketty notes, authors such as Jane Austen and HonorĂ© de Balzac "depicted the effects of inequality with a verisimilitude and evocative power that no statistical analysis can match."

This is an important point. Numerical tables simply cannot capture the deep-seated sense of social standing and expectations of deference that permeate a hierarchical society. Those familiar with the culture of the Indian subcontinent will understand this well. There are many oppressive distinctions that remain salient in modern society but we at least pay lip service to the creed that we are all created equal and endowed with certain inalienable rights. The sustainability of significant wealth inequality in the face of this creed depends on the effectiveness of what Piketty calls "the apparatus of justification." But no matter how effective this apparatus, there is a limit to the extent of wealth inequality that is consistent with the survival of this creed.

This is how I interpret Piketty's main message: if the historically significant emergence of a propertied middle class were to be reversed, social and political tremors would follow. But how are we to evaluate his claim that such a reversal is inevitable in the absence of a global tax on capital? His argument depends on interactions between demographic change, productivity growth, and the distribution of income, and without a well-articulated theory that features all these components in a unified manner, I have no way of evaluating it with much confidence.

Piketty's attitude towards theory in economics is dismissive; he claims that it involves “immoderate use of mathematical models, which are frequently no more than an excuse for occupying the terrain and masking the vacuity of the content.” This criticism is not entirely undeserved. It is nevertheless my hope that the book will stimulate theorists to think through the interactions between fertility, technology, and distribution in a serious way. Without this, I don't see how Piketty's predictions can be properly evaluated, or even fully understood. 

Sunday, April 06, 2014

Superfluous Financial Intermediation

I'm only about halfway through Flash Boys but have already come across a couple of striking examples of what might charitably be called superfluous financial intermediation.

This is the practice of inserting oneself between a buyer and a seller of an asset, when both parties have already communicated to the market a willingness to trade at a mutually acceptable price. If the intermediary were simply absent from the marketplace, a trade would occur between the parties virtually instantaneously at a single price that is acceptable to both. Instead, both parties trade against the intermediary, at different prices. The intermediary captures the spread at the expense of the parties who wish to transact, adds nothing to liquidity in the market for the asset, and doubles the notional volume of trade.

The first example may be summarized as follows. A hundred thousand shares in a company have been offered for sale at a specified price across multiple exchanges. A single buyer wishes to purchase the whole lot and is willing to pay the asked price. He places a single buy order to this effect. The order first reaches BATS, where it is partially filled for ten thousand shares; it is then routed to the other exchanges for completion. An intermediary, having seen the original buy order on arrival at BATS, places orders to buy the remaining ninety thousand shares on the other exchanges. This latter order travels faster and trades first, so the original buyer receives only partial fulfillment. The intermediary immediately posts offers to sell ninety thousand shares at a slightly higher price, which the original buyer is likely to accept. All this in a matter of milliseconds.

The intermediary here is serving no useful economic function. Volume is significantly higher than it otherwise would have been, but there has been no increase in market liquidity. Had there been no intermediary present, the buyer and sellers would have transacted without any discernible delay, at a price that would have been better for the buyer and no worse for the sellers. Furthermore, an order is allowed to trade ahead of one that made its first contact with the market at an earlier point in time.

The second example involves interactions between a dark pool and the public markets. Suppose that the highest bid price for a stock in the public exchanges is $100.00, and the lowest ask is $100.10. An individual submits a bid for a thousand shares at $100.05 to a dark pool, where it remains invisible and awaits a matching order. Shortly thereafter, a sell order for a thousand shares at $100.01 is placed at a public exchange. These orders are compatible and should trade against each other at a single price. Instead, both trade against an intermediary, which buys at the lower price, sells at the higher price, and captures the spread.

As in the first example, the intermediary is not providing any benefit to either transacting party, and is not adding liquidity to the market for the asset. Volume is doubled but no economic purpose is served. Transactions that were about to occur anyway are preempted by a fraction of a second, and a net transfer of resources from investors to intermediaries is the only lasting consequence.

Michael Lewis has focused on practices such as these because their social wastefulness and fundamental unfairness is so transparent. But it's important to recognize that most of the strategies implemented by high frequency trading firms may not be quite so easy to classify or condemn. For instance, how is one to evaluate trading based on short term price forecasts based on genuinely public information? I have tried to argue in earlier posts that the proliferation of such information extracting strategies can give rise to greater price volatility. Furthermore, an arms race among intermediaries willing to sink significant resources into securing the slightest of speed advantages must ultimately be paid for by investors. This is an immediate consequence of what I like to call Bogle's Law:
It is the iron law of the markets, the undefiable rules of arithmetic: Gross return in the market, less the costs of financial intermediation, equals the net return actually delivered to market participants.
I hope that the minor factual errors in Flash Boys won't detract from the book's main message, or derail the important and overdue debate that it has predictably stirred. By focusing on the most egregious practices Lewis has already picked the low-hanging fruit. What remains to be figured out is how typical such practices really are. Taking full account of the range of strategies used by high frequency traders, to what extent are our asset markets characterized by superfluous financial intermediation?

---

Update (4/11). It took me a while to get through it but I’ve now finished the book. It’s well worth reading. Although the public discussion of Flash Boys has been largely focused on high frequency trading, the two most damning claims in the book concern broker-dealers and the SEC.

Lewis provides evidence to suggest that some broker-dealers direct trades to their own dark pools at the expense of their customers. Brokers with less than a ten percent market share in equities trading mysteriously manage to execute more than half of their customers’ orders in their own dark pools rather than in the wider market. This is peculiar because for any given order, the likelihood that the best matching bid or offer is found in a broker’s internal dark pool should roughly match the broker’s market share in equities trading. Instead, a small portion of the order is traded at external venues in a manner that allows the information content of the order to leak out. This results in a price response on other exchanges, allowing the internal dark pool to then provide the best match.

There’s also an account of a meeting between Brad Katsuyama, the book’s main protagonist, and the SEC’s Division of Trading and Markets that is just jaw-dropping. Katsuyama had discovered the reason why his large orders were only partially filled even though there seemed to be enough offers available across all exchanges for complete fulfillment (the first example above). In order to prevent their orders from being front-run after their first contact with the market, Katsuyama and his team developed a simple but ingenious defense. They split each order into components that matched the offers available at the various exchanges, and then submitted the components at carefully calibrated intervals (separated by microseconds) so that they would arrive at their respective exchanges simultaneously. The program written to accomplish this was subsequently called Thor. Katsuyama met with the SEC to explain how Thor worked, and was astonished to find that some of the younger staffers thought that the program, designed to protect fundamental traders from being front-run, was unfair to the high-frequency outfits whose strategies were being rendered ineffective.

This account, if accurate, reveals a truly astonishing failure within the SEC to understand the agency’s primary mandate. If this is the state of our regulatory infrastructure then there really is little hope for reform.